Faith, Belief, and Knowledge
When asked; "What is
faith?" a religious person may immediately point out certain articles of
faith:
"God
exists."
"There is an eternal afterlife."
"God forgives us for our sins."
"God wrote a book."
Such statements (articles) will
certainly narrate an individual's faith in terms of what it consists in. While
this may tell us what that individual has faith in, it does not answer the
question as to what faith is. To approach the later question we may compare
faith to other states of being such as belief and knowledge.
Some people treat faith as if it
were one among many different types of belief. To "believe" something
in this sense is to accept it as true. One's belief that a particular political
candidate is the best for the job, and one's belief that the next winter will
be severe, and one's belief that there is life on other planets in the
universe, and one's belief that God created the heavens and the earth, are thus
all on the same conceptual level. The only differences among
these is the content, that is the statement accepted as true.
Few of the religious faithful (I
think) will accept this equivalence. Something about religious
faith, it seems, sets it apart from the other forms of belief. This is one
reason why simply attesting to article of faith does not answer the question;
"What is faith?" Insisting on the content alone adds support
to the view that faith is just another kind of belief.
Here is one way to distinguish faith
from ordinary belief. With many beliefs it is consistent to say; "I do
believe this, but I may be wrong". That is, we may accept something as
true while still holding open the possibility that it may turn out to be false.
I can believe that "There must be other life in the universe" while
allowing the possibility that perhaps there is not. Religious faith does not
seem to work this way. One cannot so clearly say; I have faith in God the
creator" while also holding that perhaps there is no God or creator at
all. Faith need not be rigid, but it implies a stronger relation to what is
held than does ordinary belief. Faith and belief are
not identical.
Perhaps, then, faith is really a
form of knowledge. Like faith, it would be odd to claim to know something while
holding that it may in fact be false. When someone says they know something, we
typically may ask them how they know it. So asking is a request for the reasons
or evidence one has for what is said to be known. If a person is unable to
provide reasons or evidence, we have cause to doubt their knowledge. If I were
to say; "I don't just believe that there is life on other planets in the
universe, I know it", I will be obliged to offer my evidence. If I cannot
give adequate evidence, you are within rights to say that I don't
"know" that at all.
Faith seems to differ from knowledge
in this respect. While some religious people do point to miracles, prophesies,
and sacred texts as evidence of articles of faith, it remains that much of what
faith holds is essentially mysterious. To treat religious faith as a kind of
knowledge akin to scientific knowledge or historical knowledge changes the
nature of what many people seem to express in their having faith. A deep faith
in the love of God is not a matter of having employed a systematic testing
procedure. On some accounts, for that matter, faith is precisely what one holds
to in the absence of evidence and proof. This view fits some aspects of faith.
If we had proof that God existed, there would be no need for faith. An incident
consistent with this notion of faith is described in the New Testament (John: 20.)
After his
crucifixion and death, Jesus appears to the disciples with the exception of
Thomas who is absent. Thomas refuses to believe his fellow disciple's story
without solid proof (he wants to actually touch Jesus' wounds.) A week later
Jesus appears to the disciples, this time with Thomas present. Thomas
professes his faith on the spot, but Jesus says; "You became a
believer because you saw me. |
The implication here seems to be
that anyone can be a believer given sufficient evidence and proof. But the
authentic faith persists in the absence of evidence, the lack of proof. This is
not the way we typically treat knowledge at all. In fact, if someone were to persist
in claiming to know something to be true even when the evidence and proof
failed to materialize, we would likely say "They are acting on
faith."
None of the forgoing deliberation
has settled the issue as to "what faith is." But we have begun to
work out a method of inquiry. By comparing various concepts and their uses
(i.e. faith, belief, knowledge) we are able to make distinctions and draw
similarities. This serves to turn us away from false characterizations of faith
and, perhaps, come closer to a true one. One of the first philosophers to
investigate the nature of faith by this method was St. Augustine.
(Source: An Oregon State University e-course, PHL 201, on the Great Philosophers. <http://oregonstate.edu/instruct/phl201/modules/Philosophers/Augustine/augustine_faith.html>)