COHEN v. CALIFORNIA
403 U.S. 15
Argued: February 22,
1971 Decided: June 7, 1971
MR. JUSTICE HARLAN delivered the opinion of the
Court.
This case may seem at first blush too
inconsequential to find its way into our books, but the issue it presents is of
no small constitutional significance. [403 U.S. 15, 16]
Appellant Paul Robert Cohen was
convicted in the Los Angeles Municipal Court of violating that part of
California Penal Code 415 which prohibits "maliciously and willfully
disturb[ing] the peace or quiet of any neighborhood
or person . . . by . . . offensive conduct . . . ." 1 He was
given 30 days' imprisonment. The facts upon which his conviction rests are
detailed in the opinion of the Court of Appeal of California, Second Appellate
District, as follows:
"On April 26, 1968, the defendant
was observed in the Los Angeles County Courthouse in the corridor outside of
division 20 of the municipal court wearing a jacket bearing the words `Fuck the
Draft' which were plainly visible. There were women and children present in the
corridor. The defendant was arrested. The defendant testified that he wore the
jacket knowing that the words were on the jacket as a means of informing the
public of the depth of his feelings against the Vietnam War and the draft.
"The defendant did not engage in,
nor threaten to engage in, nor did anyone as the result of his conduct [403 U.S. 15, 17] in fact commit or threaten to
commit any act of violence. The defendant did not make any loud or unusual noise,
nor was there any evidence that he uttered any sound prior to his arrest."
1 Cal. App. 3d 94, 97-98, 81 Cal. Rptr. 503, 505
(1969).
In affirming the conviction the Court of
Appeal held that "offensive conduct" means "behavior which has a
tendency to provoke others to acts of violence or to in turn disturb the
peace," and that the State had proved this element because, on the facts
of this case, "[i]t was certainly reasonably
foreseeable that such conduct might cause others to rise up to commit a violent
act against the person of the defendant or attempt to forceably
remove his jacket." 1 Cal. App. 3d, at 99-100, 81 Cal. Rptr.,
at 506. The California Supreme Court declined review by a divided vote. 2 We
brought the case here, postponing the consideration of the question of our
jurisdiction over this appeal to a hearing of the case on the merits. 399 U.S. 904 . We now
reverse.
The question of our jurisdiction need
not detain us long. Throughout the proceedings below, Cohen consistently [403 U.S. 15, 18] claimed that, as construed to
apply to the facts of this case, the statute infringed his rights to freedom of
expression guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth Amendments of the Federal
Constitution. That contention has been rejected by the highest California state
court in which review could be had. Accordingly, we are fully satisfied that
Cohen has properly invoked our jurisdiction by this appeal. 28 U.S.C. 1257 (2);
Dahnke-Walker Milling Co. v. Bondurant, 257 U.S. 282 (1921).
I
In order to lay hands on the precise issue which
this case involves, it is useful first to canvass various matters which this
record does not present.
The conviction quite clearly rests upon
the asserted offensiveness of the words Cohen used to convey his message to the
public. The only "conduct" which the State sought to punish is the
fact of communication. Thus, we deal here with a conviction resting solely upon
"speech," cf. Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. 359 (1931), not
upon any separately identifiable conduct which allegedly was intended by Cohen
to be perceived by others as expressive of particular views but which, on its
face, does not necessarily convey any message and hence arguably could be
regulated without effectively repressing Cohen's ability to express himself.
Cf. United States v. O'Brien, 391 U.S. 367 (1968).
Further, the State certainly lacks power to punish Cohen for the underlying
content of the message the inscription conveyed. At least so long as there is
no showing of an intent to incite disobedience to or disruption of the draft,
Cohen could not, consistently with the First and Fourteenth Amendments, be
punished for asserting the evident position on the inutility or immorality of
the draft his jacket reflected. Yates v.
United States, 354 U.S. 298 (1957). [403 U.S. 15, 19]
Appellant's conviction, then, rests
squarely upon his exercise of the "freedom of speech" protected from
arbitrary governmental interference by the Constitution and can be justified,
if at all, only as a valid regulation of the manner in which
he exercised that freedom, not as a permissible prohibition on the substantive
message it conveys. This does not end the inquiry, of course, for the First and
Fourteenth Amendments have never been thought to give absolute protection to
every individual to speak whenever or wherever he pleases, or to use any form
of address in any circumstances that he chooses. In this vein, too, however, we
think it important to note that several issues typically associated with such
problems are not presented here.
In the first place, Cohen was tried
under a statute applicable throughout the entire State. Any attempt to support
this conviction on the ground that the statute seeks
to preserve an appropriately decorous atmosphere in the courthouse where Cohen
was arrested must fail in the absence of any language in the statute that would
have put appellant on notice that certain kinds of otherwise permissible speech
or conduct would nevertheless, under California law, not be tolerated in
certain places. See Edwards v. South
Carolina, 372 U.S. 229, 236 -237, and
n. 11 (1963). Cf. Adderley v. Florida, 385 U.S. 39 (1966). No fair
reading of the phrase "offensive conduct" can be said sufficiently to
inform the ordinary person that distinctions between certain locations are
thereby created. 3
In the second place, as it comes to us,
this case cannot be said to fall within those relatively few categories of[403 U.S. 15,
20] instances where prior decisions have established
the power of government to deal more comprehensively with certain forms of
individual expression simply upon a showing that such a form was employed. This
is not, for example, an obscenity case. Whatever else may be necessary to give
rise to the States' broader power to prohibit obscene expression, such
expression must be, in some significant way, erotic. Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. 476 (1957). It
cannot plausibly be maintained that this vulgar allusion to the Selective
Service System would conjure up such psychic stimulation in anyone likely to be
confronted with Cohen's crudely defaced jacket.
This Court has also held that the States
are free to ban the simple use, without a demonstration of additional
justifying circumstances, of so-called "fighting words," those
personally abusive epithets which, when addressed to the ordinary citizen, are,
as a matter of common knowledge, inherently likely to provoke violent reaction.
Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568 (1942). While
the four-letter word displayed by Cohen in relation to the draft is not
uncommonly employed in a personally provocative fashion, in this instance it
was clearly not "directed to the person of the hearer." Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.S. 296, 309 (1940).
No individual actually or likely to be present could
reasonably have regarded the words on appellant's jacket as a direct personal
insult. Nor do we have here an instance of the exercise of the State's police
power to prevent a speaker from intentionally provoking a given group to
hostile reaction. Cf. Feiner v. New York, 340 U.S. 315(1951); Terminiello v. Chicago, 337 U.S. 1 (1949). There
is, as noted above, no showing that anyone who saw Cohen was in fact violently
aroused or that appellant intended such a result. [403 U.S. 15,
21]
Finally, in arguments before this Court
much has been made of the claim that Cohen's distasteful mode of expression was
thrust upon unwilling or unsuspecting viewers, and that the State might
therefore legitimately act as it did in order to
protect the sensitive from otherwise unavoidable exposure to appellant's crude
form of protest. Of course, the mere presumed presence of unwitting listeners
or viewers does not serve automatically to justify curtailing all speech
capable of giving offense. See, e. g., Organization
for a Better Austin v. Keefe, 402 U.S. 415 (1971). While
this Court has recognized that government may properly act in many situations
to prohibit intrusion into the privacy of the home of unwelcome views and ideas
which cannot be totally banned from the public dialogue, e. g., Rowan v. Post Office Dept., 397 U.S. 728 (1970), we
have at the same time consistently stressed that "we are often `captives'
outside the sanctuary of the home and subject to objectionable speech."
Id., at 738. The ability of government, consonant with the Constitution, to
shut off discourse solely to protect others from hearing it is, in other words,
dependent upon a showing that substantial privacy interests are being invaded
in an essentially intolerable manner. Any broader view of this authority would
effectively empower a majority to silence dissidents simply as a matter of
personal predilections.
In this regard, persons confronted with
Cohen's jacket were in a quite different posture than, say, those subjected to
the raucous emissions of sound trucks blaring outside their residences. Those
in the Los Angeles courthouse could effectively avoid further bombardment of
their sensibilities simply by averting their eyes. And, while it may be that one
has a more substantial claim to a recognizable privacy interest when walking
through a courthouse corridor than, for example, strolling through Central
Park, surely it is nothing like the interest in [403 U.S. 15,
22] being free from unwanted expression in the confines of
one's own home. Cf. Keefe, supra.
Given the subtlety and complexity of the factors involved, if Cohen's
"speech" was otherwise entitled to constitutional protection, we do
not think the fact that some unwilling "listeners" in a public building
may have been briefly exposed to it can serve to justify this breach of the
peace conviction where, as here, there was no evidence that persons powerless
to avoid appellant's conduct did in fact object to it, and where that portion
of the statute upon which Cohen's conviction rests evinces no concern, either
on its face or as construed by the California courts, with the special plight
of the captive auditor, but, instead, indiscriminately sweeps within its
prohibitions all "offensive conduct" that disturbs "any
neighborhood or person." Cf. Edwards
v. South Carolina, supra. 4
II
Against this background, the issue
flushed by this case stands out in bold relief. It is whether California can
excise, as "offensive conduct," one particular
scurrilous epithet from the public discourse, either upon the theory of
the court below that its use is inherently likely to cause violent reaction or
upon a more general assertion that the States, acting as guardians of public
morality, [403 U.S. 15, 23] may properly
remove this offensive word from the public vocabulary.
The rationale of the California court is
plainly untenable. At most it reflects an "undifferentiated fear or
apprehension of disturbance [which] is not enough to overcome the right to
freedom of expression." Tinker v.
Des Moines Indep. Community School Dist., 393 U.S. 503, 508 (1969).
We have been shown no evidence that substantial numbers of citizens are
standing ready to strike out physically at whoever may assault their sensibilities
with execrations like that uttered by Cohen. There may be some persons about
with such lawless and violent proclivities, but that is an insufficient base
upon which to erect, consistently with constitutional values, a governmental
power to force persons who wish to ventilate their dissident views into
avoiding particular forms of expression. The argument
amounts to little more than the self-defeating proposition that to avoid
physical censorship of one who has not sought to provoke such a response by a
hypothetical coterie of the violent and lawless, the States may more
appropriately effectuate that censorship themselves. Cf. Ashton v. Kentucky, 384 U.S. 195, 200 (1966); Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. 536, 550 -551
(1965).
Admittedly, it is not so obvious that
the First and Fourteenth Amendments must be taken to disable the States from
punishing public utterance of this unseemly expletive in
order to maintain what they regard as a suitable level of discourse
within the body politic. 5 We [403 U.S. 15, 24] think, however, that examination
and reflection will reveal the shortcomings of a contrary viewpoint.
At the outset, we cannot overemphasize
that, in our judgment, most situations where the State has a justifiable
interest in regulating speech will fall within one or more of the various
established exceptions, discussed above but not applicable here, to the usual
rule that governmental bodies may not prescribe the form or content of
individual expression. Equally important to our conclusion is the constitutional
backdrop against which our decision must be made. The constitutional right of
free expression is powerful medicine in a society as diverse and populous as
ours. It is designed and intended to remove governmental restraints from the
arena of public discussion, putting the decision as to what views shall be
voiced largely into the hands of each of us, in the hope that use of such
freedom will ultimately produce a more capable citizenry and more perfect
polity and in the belief that no other approach would comport with the premise
of individual dignity and choice upon which our political system rests. See Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 375 -377
(1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring).
To many, the immediate consequence of
this freedom may often appear to be only verbal tumult, discord, and[403 U.S.
15, 25] even offensive utterance. These are, however,
within established limits, in truth necessary side effects of the broader enduring
values which the process of open debate permits us to achieve. That the air may
at times seem filled with verbal cacophony is, in this sense not a sign of
weakness but of strength. We cannot lose sight of the fact that, in what
otherwise might seem a trifling and annoying instance of individual distasteful
abuse of a privilege, these fundamental societal values are truly implicated.
That is why "[w]holly neutral futilities . . . come under the protection
of free speech as fully as do Keats' poems or Donne's sermons," Winters v.
New York, 333 U.S. 507, 528 (1948)
(Frankfurter, J., dissenting), and why "so long as the means are peaceful,
the communication need not meet standards of acceptability," Organization for a Better Austin v. Keefe, 402 U.S. 415, 419 (1971).
Against this perception of the
constitutional policies involved, we discern certain more particularized
considerations that peculiarly call for reversal of this conviction. First, the
principle contended for by the State seems inherently boundless. How is one to
distinguish this from any other offensive word? Surely the State has no right
to cleanse public debate to the point where it is grammatically palatable to
the most squeamish among us. Yet no readily ascertainable general principle
exists for stopping short of that result were we to affirm the judgment below.
For, while the particular four-letter word being
litigated here is perhaps more distasteful than most others of its genre, it is
nevertheless often true that one man's vulgarity is another's lyric. Indeed, we
think it is largely because governmental officials cannot make principled
distinctions in this area that the Constitution leaves matters of taste and
style so largely to the individual.
Additionally, we cannot overlook the
fact, because it [403 U.S. 15, 26] is well
illustrated by the episode involved here, that much linguistic expression
serves a dual communicative function: it conveys not only ideas capable of
relatively precise, detached explication, but otherwise inexpressible emotions
as well. In fact, words are often chosen as much for their emotive as their
cognitive force. We cannot sanction the view that the Constitution, while
solicitous of the cognitive content of individual speech, has little or no
regard for that emotive function which, practically speaking, may often be the
more important element of the overall message sought to be communicated.
Indeed, as Mr. Justice Frankfurter has said, "[o]ne
of the prerogatives of American citizenship is the right to criticize public
men and measures - and that means not only informed and responsible criticism
but the freedom to speak foolishly and without moderation." Baumgartner v. United States, 322 U.S. 665, 673 -674
(1944).
Finally, and in the same vein, we cannot
indulge the facile assumption that one can forbid particular
words without also running a substantial risk of suppressing ideas in
the process. Indeed, governments might soon seize upon the censorship of particular words as a convenient guise for banning the
expression of unpopular views. We have been able, as noted above, to discern
little social benefit that might result from running the risk of opening the
door to such grave results.
It is, in sum, our judgment that, absent
a more particularized and compelling reason for its actions, the State may not,
consistently with the First and Fourteenth Amendments, make the simple public
display here involved of this single four-letter expletive a criminal offense.
Because that is the only arguably sustainable rationale for the conviction here
at issue, the judgment below must be
Reversed.
MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN, with whom THE
CHIEF JUSTICE and MR. JUSTICE BLACK join.
I dissent,
and I do so for two reasons:
1. Cohen's absurd and
immature antic, in my view, was mainly conduct and little speech. See Street v.
New York, 394 U.S.
576 (1969); Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.S.
536, 555 (1965); Giboney v. Empire Storage
Co., 336
U.S. 490, 502 (1949). The California Court of Appeal appears so to
have described it, 1 Cal. App. 3d 94, 100, 81 Cal. Rptr.
503, 507, and I cannot characterize it otherwise. Further, the case appears to
me to be well within the sphere of Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S.
568 (1942), where Mr. Justice Murphy, a known champion of First
Amendment freedoms, wrote for a unanimous bench. As a
consequence, this Court's agonizing over First Amendment values seems
misplaced and unnecessary.
2. I am not at all
certain that the California Court of Appeal's construction of 415 is now the
authoritative California construction. The Court of Appeal filed its opinion on
October 22, 1969. The Supreme Court of California declined review by a four-to-three
vote on December 17. See 1 Cal. App. 3d, at 104. A month later
on January 27, 1970, the State Supreme Court in another case construed
415, evidently for the first time. In re
Bushman, 1 Cal. 3d 767, 463 P.2d 727. Chief Justice Traynor, who was among
the dissenters to his court's refusal to take Cohen's case, wrote the majority
opinion. He held that 415 "is not unconstitutionally vague and
overbroad" and further said:
"[T]hat part of Penal Code
section 415 in question here makes punishable only wilful
and malicious conduct that is violent and endangers public safety and order or
that creates a clear and present danger that others will engage in violence of
that nature. [403 U.S. 15, 28]
". . . [It] does not make
criminal any nonviolent act unless the act incites or threatens to incite
others to violence . . . ." 1 Cal. 3d, at
773-774, 463 P.2d, at 731.
Cohen was cited in Bushman, 1 Cal. 3d, at 773, 463 P.2d, at
730, but I am not convinced that its description there and Cohen itself are
completely consistent with the "clear and present danger" standard
enunciated in Bushman. Inasmuch as this Court does not dismiss this case, it ought
to be remanded to the California Court of Appeal for reconsideration in the
light of the subsequently rendered decision by the State's highest tribunal in Bushman.
MR.
JUSTICE WHITE concurs in Paragraph 2 of MR. JUSTICE BLACKMUN'S dissenting
opinion.