An
Introduction to Political Theory and Political Philosophy
“It is
remarkable how many arguments that might be thought to be ethical or political,
and so to deal with purely practical matters, depend in fact on much deeper
philosophical issues. This is none the less true because the men of action who
put them into practice may not always be aware of it; and often the connexion
is in fact a fully conscious one. Politics
and morals, general theories of human nature, metaphysics and epistemology
cannot be separated.” W. K. C. Guthrie, The
Sophists (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1971), 4-5.
“The heavy
books of Grotius, Pufendorf, Hooker and the others, standing on [John] Locke’s
shelves and dominating intellectual activity in this field, were all
presentations of a single, synthetic system, a view of the world which
proceeded from an account of reality to an account of knowledge, and so on to
an ethic and politics.” Peter Laslett, “Introduction,” in John Locke: Two Treatises of Government, rev.ed. (New York: The New
American Library, 1960, 1965), 100.
“For neither
the classic nor Christian ethics and politics contain ‘value judgments’ but
elaborate, empirically and critically, the problems of order that derive from
philosophical anthropology as part of a general ontology. Only when ontology as
a science was lost, and when consequently ethics and politics could no longer
be understood as sciences of the order in which human nature reaches its maximal
actualization, was it possible for this realm of knowledge to become suspect as
a field of subjective, uncritical opinion.” Eric Voegelin, “Introduction,” to The New Science of Politics, in Modernity Without Restraint (Columbia:
University of Missouri Press, 2000), 96.
The Fundamental Conceptions
In college I
spent many a night deep in political argument with political friends and foes
and with no conscious thought of engaging in political theory or political
philosophy. One such discussion might very well have gone like this:
Someone
said, “I believe that the government should provide free health care to
everyone, regardless of the people’s income level.”
“I
disagree,” came the inevitable response. “Government has no business providing
free goodies to people. Individuals have a responsibility to provide—to
buy—their own medical insurance, if they wish. Government is supposed to
provide for the national security and domestic law and order, and that’s it!”
“Oh, I agree
that people should buy their own health insurance, but too many people who can
afford the insurance do not buy it and many people in this greatest nation on
earth simply cannot afford adequate health insurance and still have enough
money for food, clothing, shelter, and the other necessities. In either case,
when these uninsureds—or the uninsureds’ innocent children!—get real sick or
seriously injured, they either go without needed care or it falls on other
people or the government to take care of them anyway. The private insurance
system just does not work; it should be replaced by a national system of
government supported universal health care. Besides, adequate health care is a
human right: government is supposed to guarantee our inalienable rights.”
“So adequate
health care is now a natural right! What other rights do we have? A right to a
job? A right to free food? A right to free housing? And the government is
obligated to provide all of these? Where do you come up with this nonsense! I
agree that it is wrong for individuals to fail to provide for themselves and
their families, but most people do buy insurance, and many others would buy
health insurance if the government prohibited insurance companies from charging
outrageous, immoral prices. Let government do what it does best: regulate when
necessary to secure the common good, but government should not be the actual
provider of goods and services.”
“Wait. You
just told me that I cannot know what
rights people have, but you seem to know
that failure to provide for your own health care is wrong, that insurance
companies charge immoral prices, and that most people would buy health
insurance if the insurance was reasonably affordable, whatever that means. How
do you know any of this? It seems to
me that most people would avoid spending anything on health insurance if they
could get away with it. They would rather spend their money on creature
comforts for themselves.”
This snippet
of common conversation contained assertions relating to all five of the
fundamental conceptions of political philosophy that we will study in this
course: (1) politics (what should government do about health care); (2) ethics
(do individuals have a moral responsibility to insure themselves and companies
have a moral responsibility to charge fair prices); (3) anthropology (do
people—some of them or most of them—avoid their real needs in
favor of satisfying superficial desires); (4) epistemology (how do we really know any of this, or is it all purely a
matter of opinion); and (5) ontology-cosmology (do people have “natural” rights
or duties by simply being born into the world).
If you think
about it, we talk about these basic concepts all the time in political
discussions when we question whether government should really be doing this or
that (politics), whether this or that is truly “right” or “good” (ethics),
whether people are basically honest or dishonest, timid sheep or selfish wolves
(anthropology), whether we can actually know the answers to the questions just
asked or whether it is all just a matter of personal opinion (epistemology),
and, depending on how late into the night the discussion continues, even
whether there is meaning in life or “Is this all there is?” (ontology and
cosmology).
This class
assumes that you are interested in politics. If you want to think seriously
about politics and not simply follow one political leader or political party or
political ideology blindly in whatever direction that leader, party, or
ideology herds you, then your thinking and questioning will take you into these
five areas and thus into political theory.
Theory and Philosophy
Theory and philosophy began with the
ancient Greeks, and many of the terms necessary to understand philosophical
arguments are Greek terms. There is no better place to begin than with a review
of these terms and their most common meanings.
“Theory”
is from a Greek word (theoreo)
meaning “a looking at, a viewing; contemplation, speculation.” Theory is a type
of human action: inspecting or examining something. Political theory is the examination of political (from the Greek word for city-state, polis) things. In this classical sense, theory is part of any
scientific undertaking, for “science” generally refers to a comprehensive
effort to understand something by examining it thoroughly.
Today,
because of the influence of modern physical science, the word “theory” is often
used in the plural—theories— to refer to the articulated results of theoretical
efforts. A modern scientific theory is
an extended hypothetical argument,
which is an argument in the form of if-then statements: “If the stated
assumptions are true, then this should be the observed result because it
was caused by the assumed conditions.” A modern scientific theory proposes an
explanation of a “phenomenon”—an observable event (incidentally, it’s another
word derived from Greek).[1]
A scientific theory ties a particular phenomenon to other phenomena in
predictable, causal ways. The term “theory” is also popularly used to indicate
a hunch—a proposed explanation of something (“my theory is that the explosion
resulted from a gas leak”). In the following introduction, we shall primarily
use “theory” in the classical sense of the act of comprehensive examination
rather than in the modern senses of hypothetical arguments or explanations of
observable events.
“Philosophy,” another Greek word (philosophia, from philo, love, and sophia,
wisdom) also carries the fundamental meaning of thorough examination.[2]
Leo Strauss highlighted this connection when he said, “In the expression
‘political philosophy,’ ‘philosophy’ indicates the manner of treatment: a
treatment which both goes to the roots and is comprehensive.”[3]
Philosophy is distinguished from other studies by both its breadth and its
focus on wisdom. In ancient times, philosophy was primarily understood not as
an academic subject but as a way of living, a life devoted to the pursuit of
wisdom and truth: thus, both philosophy and theory were originally understood
to be types of human action, not intellectual “things,” like theories and
philosophies.
"Wisdom"
or sophia in turn was understood to
be knowledge of the most important things in life, the permanent things—the
nature of the universe, the meaning of life, the ultimate standards of right
and wrong. Strauss said that “philosophy’s quest for wisdom is a quest for
universal knowledge, for knowledge of the whole.”[4]
In the words of Cicero:
Those who pursue wisdom have earned the
title “philosophers,” and philosophy is nothing more or less, if you translate
the word, than the “devotion to wisdom.” This is how some older philosophers
define wisdom: it is the knowledge of everything about both gods and men and
what causes underlie nature.[5]
Socrates made a
similar point in Plato’s Republic:
"For you know, [this] consideration is about the greatest thing, a good
life and a bad one."[6]
Philosophy, originally meaning a
life-long pursuit of wisdom, is now often understood as a subject of academic
study focuses on the writings of individuals who have engaged in that pursuit.
Even the writings of Plato that argue for philosophy as a way of life that
cannot be reduced to writing are now studied as part of the material that makes
up the academic subject.[7] In
this introduction, we will use “philosophy” (and in like manner, “theory”) as
both (1) the comprehensive examination of a subject with the purpose of
obtaining wisdom and (2) as particular works reflecting that examination.[8]
Because of the closeness between the classical meanings of philosophy and
theory, we will use the two terms synonymously throughout this basic
introduction.
The purpose of this introductory
essay is to explain that though philosophy is the love of wisdom, students need
not be in love with philosophy to be able to analyze the philosophic or
theoretical writings that will be assigned in this course, to acquire a basic
understanding of the different writers that we will study, and to form coherent
opinions about their ideas and about political things. After all, as Socrates
said in Plato’s dialogue Gorgias,
"The argument is not about just any question, but about the way one should
live," and there is no subject that should be of more interest to
intelligent people, especially today.
The Components of
Philosophy: the Fundamental Conceptions
Philosophers,
in pursuit of knowledge of the whole, break the whole down into several
intellectually distinguishable subjects or questions. (1) Ontology is the study of the nature of reality, of what really and
truly exists and how it exists; within ontology, cosmology is the narrower study of the nature of the observable
universe in which we live. Together, the two studies are often described as the
subject matter of metaphysics (from
the Greek meta, after or beyond, phusis, nature). (2) Epistemology refers to questions about
what we can know and how we can know it. (3) Anthropology (from the Greek word for man, anthropos) is the study of man, his essential nature and how people
behave. The suffix “-logy” of these terms may be translated as “the science of”
or “the study of”; it is from the Greek word logos, which originally meant “word” or “speech” but came to
signify more broadly what we generally refer to as “reason.” (4) Ethics is the study of what is right
and wrong, good and evil, for individual human beings. And (5) politics is the study of the right
order and government of an organized community. There are other objects of
philosophic study (such as logic and aesthetics), and the bumper-sticker
definitions given here do not even scratch the surface in explaining the
studies just listed, but this list of terms—all of which are derived from Greek
words—gives us an idea of the content that a course in political philosophy
might contain. Wisdom as “knowledge of the whole,” as knowledge of all things,
is understood to comprehend these particular studies in an effort to see their
relationships to each other.
We
should also note that the Great Religions also address each of these subjects.
They provide us with an understanding of the origins and the nature of the
universe, a theory of knowledge that places revelation and faith beside reason
as ways of knowing, an understanding of the nature of man and of what is
morally right and wrong, and, in some but not all of the religions, a
prescription for good government. In our studies this semester, we will make
frequent references to religions and religious ideas. You might be interested
to know that the very term “theology” was invented by Plato to describe the
rational discussion of God and the divine.
Very few written philosophical works
include every one of these studies. Most philosophical works focus on one
subject or another. A thorough discussion of human nature, or of right and
wrong, or of political order, however, must lead to considerations of ontology
and epistemology, and it must be internally consistent (logical) as well as
accurate in its description of the subject matter.
Political
philosophy, in particular, depends on considerations of the other four subjects
just mentioned—ontology, epistemology, anthropology, and ethics—leading some
philosophers to call it the highest or most comprehensive philosophic study.
Aristotle made this claim when, in his most famous work on ethics, not on politics, he called politics, not ethics, the “master science”:
Will
not then a knowledge of this Supreme Good be also of great practical importance
for the conduct of life? Will it not better enable us to attain what is
fitting, like archers having a target to aim at? If this be so, we ought to
make an attempt to determine at all events in outline what exactly this Supreme
Good is, and of which of the theoretical or practical sciences it is the
object. Now it would be agreed that it must be the object of the most
authoritative of the sciences—some science which is pre-eminently a
master-craft. But such is manifestly the science of Politics.[9]
Plato, speaking through Socrates, suggested much the same
thing in the passages we cited above from the Republic and the Gorgias.
Statements about the importance of
political theory are not confined to the thinkers of ancient Greece. Eric
Voegelin, a twentieth-century political philosopher we cited earlier, generally
referred to the comprehensive study of politics as “political science” rather
than as political philosophy. In criticizing what he called the
"degradation of political science to a handmaid of the powers that
be," Voegelin called for the restoration of political science "to its
full grandeur as the science of human existence in society and history, as well
as of the principles of order in general."[10] Leo Strauss, another important
twentieth-century philosopher quoted above, expressed a similar point:
“Originally political philosophy was identical with political science, and it
was the all-embracing study of human affairs.” As part of the larger enterprise
of philosophy in general, which Strauss says is “the humanizing quest for the
eternal order," “the theme of political philosophy is mankind’s great
objectives, freedom and government of empire—objectives which are capable of
lifting all men beyond their poor selves.”[11]
Philosophical writings come to us in
many different forms—Plato’s dramatic dialogues, Aristotle's lecture notes,
Lucretius’s poetry, Gnostic "gospels," St. Augustine's letters and
essays, St. Thomas's scholastic demonstrations, and Hobbes's, Locke’s, and
Rousseau’s treatises or book-length analyses of politics and other subjects.
Regardless of the form, the content of these writings is ideas—“speculative
thought" as Henri Frankfort calls it—that attempt to make sense of a
complex and multi-faceted part of life by placing it within the context of the
whole of reality. For most students, getting a handle on ideas and abstract
thought takes practice and requires some getting used to. It is important to
remember when reading the assigned works that the writers were intelligent
individuals who had definite things to say and that each said what he had to
say in an orderly way that has withstood the test of time. This is why these
works are called "classics." The writers did not compose
stream-of-consciousness monologues or
"first-thing-that-pops-into-my-mind" mixtures of hot air and other gases. The writings are purposefully structured and
can be systematically analyzed. Using a dictionary and the tools provided in
this essay, you should read the assigned works sympathetically first, trying to
understand their structure and detail before turning to criticism. Make sure
that you have a basic grasp of the writings before you attempt to evaluate
them.
But even more important to remember
is that these writers are not necessarily correct in what they say; indeed,
since most of the assigned writers contradict at least one other writer that
you will read, they cannot all be
correct. What follows from this is that you, Lowly Student, after analyzing the
readings must then evaluate them and make your own judgment about them. You
must develop a critical distance between your own mind and judgment and the
ideas and arguments you are considering. You must do this, or else you will be simply swept downstream by
arguments that may not be sound or by leaders who make or follow unsound
arguments themselves. If these arguments and leaders use your willing support
to achieve bad ends, you are complicit, and complicity itself is blameworthy.[12]
If you can come to terms with the writers that are assigned in this course, you
will be well positioned to evaluate the arguments of the legion of lesser
writers who, although they are intelligent and may have sound ideas, are not of
the same high caliber as the "greats" that we will read.
All of the
writers we study this semester wrote comprehensively on politics; in fact, we
will read material from most of the great contributors to Western political
philosophy who lived during the two millennia from the fifth century B.C. to
the seventeenth century A.D.: Plato, Aristotle, St. Augustine, St. Thomas
Aquinas, Thomas Hobbes, and John Locke, as well as reading the great poem of
Lucretius and excerpts from the writings of Epicurus, Cicero, Epictetus, and
Marcus Aurelius. These writings must be analyzed in terms of the ideas they
reflect regarding metaphysics, epistemology, anthropology, ethics, and politics.
During the second semester (POL 211),
when the assigned writings generally begin in the late seventeenth century and
end in the present day, many of the writers are not and never will be
considered among the "greats," in part because their writings do not
cover the full range of philosophical subjects. Many of the works we read in
the second semester focus on particular aspects of politics and say little or
nothing about ontology, epistemology, and so on. Still, once you have become
familiar with the classics, you should be able to make an educated guess about
a writer’s likely views regarding the nature of the universe, the nature of
man, and so forth. You will be able to fill in the ontological and the other
blanks.
Philosophic Traditions
Finally, we will find that there
seem to be only so many distinct philosophical alternatives regarding each of
the fundamental conceptions and that certain ontological positions mesh neatly
with certain epistemological, anthropological, ethical, and political
positions. Certainly, there are infinite gradations and variations within each
alternative, but the fundamental positions on the nature of the universe, of
knowledge, of human nature, of the ultimate standard of right and wrong, and of
the function of government begin to settle into a few familiar groups that
enable you to rationally compare and contrast one writer to another. The course is a study of the five
fundamental conceptions in four broad patterns or traditions: (1) the
Epicurean or Epicurean-modern tradition, (2) the Classical tradition, (3) the
Classical-Christian tradition, and (4) the gnostic or esoteric tradition, which
includes Gnostic and Hermeticist thought.
The
Epicurean tradition, beginning with the Greek philosophers Leucippus, Democritus,
and Epicurus, strongly influenced modern political philosophy, especially
English political philosophy after the sixteenth century, so we also use the
term “modern” to refer to the English Epicureans Thomas Hobbes and John Locke.
The Classical philosophic tradition refers not to all of the philosophers of
Classical Greece, but primarily to Plato and Aristotle, and later the Stoics.
In the Middle Ages, Plato and Aristotle strongly influenced the theology and
philosophic outlooks of many, but certainly not all, Jewish, Christian, and
Muslim theologians and philosophers. Each of these religions had a strong
current of Classical thought running through it for at least part of its
history. Writings from St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas will serve as representative
of this Classical religious thought, though we could also use writings from the
Muslims Averroes, Al-farabi, and Avicenna, as well as the Jewish philosopher
Maimonides. The fourth tradition, which we may generally call the esoteric
tradition or gnostic (with a small “g”) tradition, includes materials by
ancient Gnostic and Hermeticist writers. The Gnostics were an ancient religion
that had a distinctive cosmology that colored their anthropology, ethics, and
politics. The Hermetic or Hermeticist tradition, also referred to by itself as
the “esoteric” tradition, has been found in recent times to have been an
influential source of ideas throughout Western history. Though it differed
significantly from Gnostic thought in several regards, Hermeticism shared with
Gnosticism a central focus on certain knowledge, or “gnosis” (Greek) that holds
the key to understanding and salvation.
As we go through the semester, you
might want to make up a grid with five rows or columns representing the five
fundamental conceptions and with four or five intersecting rows or columns
representing the four (five, if you decide to treat Hermeticism as distinct
from Gnosticism) traditions we will be studying.
|
Epicurean tradition |
Classical tradition |
Classical-Christian tradition |
Esoteric tradition |
Ontology |
|
|
|
|
Epistemology |
|
|
|
|
Anthropology |
|
|
|
|
Ethics |
|
|
|
|
Politics |
|
|
|
|
The following notes will help you to recognize the different
fundamental conceptions and will get you started on your way.
Fundamental
Concepts: Ontology and Cosmology
Ontology
(Greek on, gen. ontos, “of that which exists”) is the study of the nature of
reality, of what truly is, or,
simply, the study of being—what it
means to be. Ontology poses a cluster
of questions about reality, about what really exists: does reality have a
structure? If so, what is its structure, or, to ask the same thing, what is the
order of being? How is being or reality constituted? Cosmology is the narrower
study of the cosmos (yes, it’s
another Greek word: this one means good order, good behavior; or, from its
perfect order, the world or the universe). Cosmogony is the study of the origin
of the universe (Greek again: cosmos-genesis). Often, if a writer discusses one
of these studies, he discusses the other, but not always.
Ontology and cosmology are closely
related inquiries. Cosmology focuses on the world in which we live, the world
that we experience—including outer space, the galaxies, the universe—and
cosmogony asks where all of this came from. Ontology includes these studies of
the cosmos, but also pursues the broader and often puzzling questions of
appearance and reality such as “What is real?” “Is only matter real?” “Is only
what we can observe with our senses real?” “Are relationships between things
real?” “What is the true nature of this?” “What is the essence of that?” “Are
there ‘natures’ and ‘essences’?” Together, the three subjects make up the
greater study of metaphysics (Greek: meta,
after or beyond, and physics, the
study of observable or empirical phenomena).
Eric Voegelin has said that reality
consists of the natural, the human (individual and social), and the divine. If
we refer to “nature” as that which is not man-made, might it not also include
gods? Or might it have been made by God? For most of man’s recorded history, it
went without saying that reality included both divine and non-divine, sacred
and profane: recall Cicero’s definition of “wisdom” quoted above: “it is
knowledge of everything about both gods and men and what causes underlie
nature.” The tradition of natural theology reflects this essential bond between
the natural and the divine. But these two dimensions of reality are distinct.
In describing early man’s fundamental experiences of the sacred in the midst of
the profane, every-day world, Mircea Eliade says, “The sacred always manifests
itself as a reality of a wholly different order from ‘natural’ realities.”[13] Primitive man experienced the sacred as more
real than the natural order, as “the only real
and real-ly existing space” and time.[14]
Voegelin’s and Eliade’s remarks reflect ontological
observations.
And what about human creations or
“artifacts”? Just as mountains, trees, and stars, so also man is a part of
nature, but human creations are fundamentally different from what nature
creates and are often of more interest to us and especially to students of
politics. One of man’s principal creations is ideas: are ideas—the very ideas
that we have about the natural and the supernatural—real? What is their nature? Plato, the founder of
political science, argued that ideas of things are more real than the substance
of those ideas that we grasp through perception; Karl Marx, to name just one of
many thinkers, argued that they were less real.
These questions, primary in the sense
that they all simply ask about the reality of things, are followed by questions about the structure of what is
real. What are the relationships between various parts of being? What is the
relationship between ideas and the fundamental experiences that the ideas
articulate? Why do we call certain articles of furniture, though of multiple
shapes and sizes, all “chairs”? Is this general idea or universal “chair” real
and independent of man’s thought, or is it merely a construct, a mentally
created tool, less real than the objects we perceive? Is the world in which we
live imbued with divine purpose and intention? Are some parts of nature
intended to be the means for achieving further natural ends? And if so, who
intended them? Do aspects of the structure of reality serve as clues or
standards for proper human action: is there a natural moral order?
Different writers have answered these
questions in fundamentally different ways. What kinds of arguments and ideas
have they offered? What clues to their positions should you look for? One
question you might ask is whether the philosopher says or whether he implicitly
assumes that the world is an orderly place or that the world has no apparent
order. If there is a natural order—an
order not imposed on nature by man, remember, but one that exists independently
of human will—what kind of an order is it?
Aristotle,
for example, said that there was a natural order to the world based on the
purposes or functions that characterized each natural thing, including as
natural things man and the polis in which he lived. God, the source of these
purposes, was part of nature itself. The Epicureans, by contrast, said that
there is no discoverable natural order in the world or in man or society (though
Epicurus said that gods were part of nature while Hobbes maintained that God
was outside of nature). The only order we can find in the world according to
Hobbes is that which is imposed upon it by us human animals. As we shall see,
different conclusions about anthropology, ethics, and politics follow
reasonably from these different positions.
Cosmogonically,
we cannot draw any hard and fast inferences from particular cosmologies to
particular arguments about the origins of the universe. Hobbes, for example,
affirmed the existence of the Christian God as Creator and denied that he was
himself an atheist or that his cosmology was consistent only with an atheistic
position, but he also denied the existence of a discernible cosmic order. The
Navajo understand some stars to have been divinely placed in the sky as
constellations and other starts to have been randomly blown into space by the
Coyote. Orthodox Christian, Jewish, and Muslim thinkers, on the other hand,
understand the world as an orderly place because it was coherently created by
God the Creator of Heaven and Earth. God exists beyond his creation: he
transcends nature and is therefore super-natural.
Aristotle's Supreme Being was not a creator that created the universe and thus
made it an orderly structure; indeed, Aristotle's god was not a supernatural
being at all—the Prime Mover was part of the natural universe. The Gnostics
viewed the world as governed by a natural order created by a supernatural god;
indeed, the Gnostics conceived of this order as more rigorous and systematic
than either the classical or the Christian thinkers. For Gnostics, the world
order was “systematic,” but systematically bad because it was created by a bad
god, an inferior god: the “true” God was beyond the creator god: he was super-supernatural. For Hermeticist
thinkers, man stands as a co-creator of a continually developing cosmos, a
god-in-waiting—a magus. Clearly, these writers present a broad range of
cosmological alternatives, and just as clearly questions of the origins and the
nature of the world are as religious as they are philosophic.
Speculations
about what is real and what reality consists of are ontological speculations.
They can be tied closely to cosmological speculation about the universe, but they
can also be understood independently from their cosmological foundations. In
the political writings that we shall be reading, there will be explicit and
implicit references to both ontology and cosmology: if the discussions are
explicit, note them; if the writings do not make any explicit references to
ontology or cosmology, try to infer what positions the author takes on these
issues from what he says about other matters. Of all the fundamental concepts
we need to know, ontology is probably the most difficult to master because it
is the most abstract subject, yet we confront questions about reality and
appearance in our lives every day. Like all of the fundamental conceptions, the
concepts of ontology and cosmology are familiar to us in very common sense
ways; what we must do in this course is get a handle not on concrete examples
of reality and appearance, but on the very concepts of “reality” and
“appearance.”
Epistemology
Ontology is
inextricably tied to epistemology (Greek, episteme,
knowledge, science). To assert that something exists is to claim that we can know that it exists. If reality consists
of natural, supernatural, and human elements, how can we know or understand the
natural, the divine, and the human? Through reason, revelation, faith, and
self-knowledge, perhaps; at least these modes of understanding have often been
suggested as the ways that we know these three modes of being.
When we said above that Hobbes argued
that there was no discernible natural order, our statement was a bit
misleading. Though we made the statement in the discussion of ontology,
Hobbes’s statement is more correctly an epistemological, not an ontological,
statement: “There is no discernible
order,” not “there is no order.” Hobbes’s statement is about what we can know,
not about what there is. Even if there is a natural, divine, psychic, or social
order—and there may well be—we might not be able to discover it, says Hobbes.
Epistemology
asks what we can know and how we can know it. It is sometimes referred to as
the theory of knowledge. Psychologists study it in terms of “modes of
cognition.” Like ontology, this subject is perhaps new to you, but it is
surprisingly important for political philosophy because it concerns what we can
know about the world and about standards of behavior. Hobbes, for example,
began his major work on politics with a dozen chapters on epistemology, and the
core of the greatest work of political theory, Plato’s Republic, is a discussion of epistemology and ontology, for these
two studies are opposite sides of the same coin.
The assigned
readings will expose us to a range of epistemological positions. For some
writers, human beings possess an intellectual ability to discern—to intuit—the structure of reality, both
natural and man-made, through careful examination and thinking. This ability is
generally called rationality or reason, but because these two terms are
used widely and are associated with significantly different concepts, the
intuitive ability in particular is often referred to as noetic apprehension, from the Greek word nous. This conception of reason is the basis for the classical
concepts of philosophy and theory, as we have defined them. Classical
philosophers thought that reason allowed man to plug into the world, so to speak,
and discern order in an immediate, intuitive way. These fundamental experiences
of order had to be pondered and figured out, but the logical reasoning needed
for this articulation was based on such fundamental human experiences, and the
human mind was our connection with the order of being. This view is sometimes
identified as the correspondence
theory of truth: our true ideas correspond with reality—reality is truth.
Other writers focus on the logic
component of reason and identify reason exclusively with the ability to think
logically: “reason in this sense is nothing but reckoning (that is, adding and
subtracting) of the consequences of general names agreed upon for marking and
signifying our thoughts.”[15]
The connection of our thoughts with reality—our ability to intuit or discern
the order of reality through perception—is missing here. The correspondence of
our thoughts with reality and hence the correspondence theory of truth is not
possible. As Hobbes said, “For true and false are attributes of speech, not of
things. And where speech is not, there is neither truth nor falsehood.” We must
hypothesize and experiment in order to gain a working or pragmatic
understanding of the world in which we live, but we can never truly know the order to reality. This is the
conception of reason that underlies positivism and much modern science, but it
was present in the ancient world as well. This view is sometimes identified
with the pragmatic theory or with the
consistency theory of truth, or both.
For some writers, our intellect
allows us to discern only part of the order of being; revelation is necessary
to enlarge or complete the picture. That which is known by revelation is and
must be revealed to us by others because we cannot reason it out on our own. Faith
usually means the acceptance or commitment to truth that cannot be reasoned out
on our own—especially the truth revealed to someone else by revelation. The
relationship between reason and revelation poses a whole battery of difficult
questions. If reason and revelation are fundamentally incompatible ways of
obtaining wisdom, then the two, unless carefully kept within their appropriate
respective bounds, are antithetical. Depending on the breadth of possible
knowledge that one attributes to revelation, for instance, the breadth of
rationality is expanded or constricted. Thus the view that reason is identical
with logic, which we outlined above, is as consistent with the deeply religious
outlook of a Tertullian as it is with the more obscure religious attitude of a
Hobbes. An atheist’s conception of reason and wisdom might leave little room
for faith and divine revelation.
Alternatively, reason and revelation
may be understood to complement one another—not “either-or” but “both-and”—and
again Cicero’s statement is relevant: philosophy is devotion to wisdom, and
wisdom is the knowledge of everything about gods and men and what causes
underlie nature. St. Augustine’s oft repeated statement is also an example:
“For God will aid us and will make us understand what we believe. This is the
course prescribed by the prophet who says, ‘Unless you believe, you shall not
understand.’” The knowledge of gods might be within the scope of reason,
classically understood, but the knowledge might require revelation. If reason is
understood to include the intuitive or immediate discernment of reality, as it
was by the Classical philosophers Plato and Aristotle, and if revelation is
also a form of immediate knowledge—knowledge that does not have to be figured
out or verified by observation and testing—the intuitive reason and revelation
are very close in nature. In Plato’s mystical experience of the Good, for
example, reason and revelation merge to the point of indistinguishability. In
St. Augustine’s undeniably reasonable discussions of man, society, and God, the
essentially rational disciplines of philosophy and theology similarly merge.
Both writers experience a direct connection with a transcendent divinity and
make their experiences the basis of their subsequent reasoning and their claims
to wisdom.
Therefore,
it is particularly important to focus on the writers’ conceptions of reason in
the assigned readings. Look for the writers’ discussions of what rationality is
and whether it enables us to obtain ontological and ethical knowledge or
whether the nature of the universe and the nature of right and wrong are
unknowable and matters for human convention or divine revelation.
Philosophical and Empirical Anthropology: the Nature of Man
v. Human Nature
Politics is
preeminently an enterprise of human beings, and almost everything about people
is relevant to political theory. Because the subject is so broad, anthropology,
the study of man in general, is broken down into two areas of study, philosophical anthropology and empirical anthropology, and the second area is broken down even
further. Philosophical anthropology is actually an ontological study: what is
the nature of man? Does man fit into a larger natural order, and if so how?
What makes a human being essentially
human? Empirical anthropology is the study of observable human behavior. How do
people usually behave? Clearly, psychology, sociology, and the other social
sciences are types of empirical anthropology that study different areas of
human behavior, but political theory is more precisely interested in those
aspects of human behavior or human nature
that are significant for politics.
All of us from a very early age have
given some thought to these questions, typically to those of empirical
anthropology first: Are people basically honest or dishonest? Selfish or
sympathetic? Strong-willed or weak-willed? What is the normal human response to this or that situation? What is the natural response? What’s the difference,
if any? All of us must formulate some responses to these basic questions in
order to survive and prosper.
Politics, on the other hand, looks at
man from the perspective of ordering his individual behavior as one among many
people living together: if there is no human society, there is no need for
government and politics is irrelevant. Are people naturally peaceful or
naturally warlike? Is group living naturally peaceful or is it full of
conflict? Can people be trained or educated to adopt peaceful—or
violent—approaches to life? Are people basically independent-minded leaders or
followers? Can people learn these behaviors? Are human beings essentially
rational or irrational? None of the above? The answer to these questions might
be based on observations of human behavior; thus we call this empirical anthropology. The social
sciences and most American political science courses—international relations,
political parties and interest groups, voting behavior, and the like—focus on
this aspect of anthropology. We will find significantly different views of
human nature expressed all across the four traditions that we study, within and
without the traditions. No tradition is tied to one particular understanding of
human nature.
There is
another aspect of man, however, that cannot be discovered by mere observation, and
here the different traditions do take distinctively different positions. If a
philosopher maintains that there is an order to reality, and if man is part of
reality, then the norms appropriate to man are basically like the norms
applying to other parts of reality, and man can be understood fundamentally as
having a natural order—a nature, an essential function or purpose—himself. If
no natural order exists, then man obviously cannot be part of it, and human
nature—man’s essence or being—is radically independent of the world in which he
lives. This independence may also be true if the natural order in which man
lives is understood to be fundamentally bad or if man’s true nature is to
participate in the creation of the cosmos. When the focus of the discussion is
on the nature of man and his place in reality, we call the discussion philosophical anthropology.
Politics is
a human inquiry, and the writers that we will study are some of the greatest
students in history of the way people think and behave, but novelists,
playwrights, and people in the most unlikely walks of life may also be keen
students of human nature. All of them will have something to say about human
nature even if they say little about cosmology or epistemology in the writings
that we will study. But all of us have
our own ideas about human nature, too. This is one area in which our own ideas
can serve as standards for our evaluation of the “great” philosophers that we
will read.
Ethics
As
understood by Aristotle, ethics is the study of what conduct is right and wrong
for individuals. In this sense, ethics is synonymous with morals or morality,
though recent academic usage of the term “moral” has extended its meaning to
the general question of the very nature of goodness itself. As an analytical
tool for political philosophy, we shall use “ethics” in its original, more
limited, Aristotelian meaning.
Despite the
many opinions on the question of right and wrong conduct, there seem to be a
few general approaches into which the different opinions and theories fit. For
one thing, the ultimate standards or principles of right and wrong may be
traced back to nature, or back to God, or merely back to man. The Greek
sophists first made this distinction in their discussions of physis and nomos—of nature versus “convention,” which means the product of
human agreement or custom or tradition. If the ultimate principles are by physis, by nature, then their truth and
authority is independent of human will and opinion. All of us might be wrong on
what is truly right or wrong in a particular instance—or even wrong all the
time. Because God or the divine is also independent of human will, we may
provisionally include divine sources under the category of physis here. If the ultimate principles are conventional, then
their “truth” depends on decisions and opinions of human beings, and opinions
may change over time. Thus, moral principles might be authoritatively
determined by a majority of the people, or by an elected leader, or by a wise
man, or by a bully. This distinction also gives rise to the popular opposition
of “absolute” standards to “relative” standards. In this sense, natural
standards are absolute—they are independent of human opinion and always the
same everywhere; conventional standards are relative—they depend on different
cultures and societies. But we shall see that the distinction is not that
simple.
Ethical
theories are thus tied closely to ontological and epistemological concepts. If
the world in which we live has no discernible order, we say that it has no
“natural order,” and the whole basis for accepting ethical norms because they
are “by nature” is destroyed. Certainly, some have inferred a natural “survival
of the fittest” or “kill or be killed” principle of ethics; in fact, this was essentially
the idea first identified with the term “natural law” by Callicles in Plato’s Gorgias. But the idea that the natural
order provides authoritative norms for human action is usually identified with
the belief that nature is good, that nature provides man with purposes and
goals appropriate to being human, and that man’s duty in life is to fulfill
these natural purposes as best he can. If nature is bad, then the true source
of norms (assuming here that the very meaning of ethical norm is good norm) must be man via convention or
God by revelation.
The idea
that all norms are conventional is usually, but not always, identified with the
ontological position that reality—nature—does not provide man with norms to
live by and that man must devise his own norms. Often these norms are
deontological: laws, customs, rules of etiquette and propriety. Sometimes they
are teleological: anything that furthers the revolution or advances us toward
some Summum Bonum is right and good,
anything that hampers such progress is bad. Divine commands or rules may also
be the highest authority, whether or not there is a discernible order of being.
Indeed, the order of nature might be bad and only the commands of God can
provide sound standards of action.
And with the
word “discernible” we are brought to the equally relevant consideration of
epistemology: is a natural moral order discernible? By “discernible” we mean
discoverable or cognizable by reason. Can we rationally figure out what is
right and wrong? If the sole source of ethical norms is conventional or divine,
and thus probably articulated in the form of rules and customs, then how can we
discern them and determine what they are? Usually, we must be told what they
are either by the human legislator or by God; and if by God, then we usually
learn them by His revealing them: that is, we learn by revelation, not by
reason. The norms will be essentially arbitrary, not subject to rational
inquiry, and the source of the norms may be something powerful, revered, or good,
or some combination of these three. Both reason and revelation or reason and
faith together may be the means of discernment if we hold that ethical truth
can be determined by human wisdom or practical wisdom.
Ethical
questions also pose the question of “authority,” sometimes redundantly referred
to as the question of “legitimate authority.” Here it is useful to distinguish
relationships of “authority and obligation” from those of “coercion and
obedience.”[16]
Authority is usually said to create obligation or duty: we are obligated to act
in accordance with authority; moral duties define good acts. Coercion or force,
while it can certainly stimulate obedience, cannot create obligation or duty.
Some of the things we are forced to do are bad or wrong: we cannot be said to
have a duty to do them, and we should not be held morally responsible for them.
Thus, participating at gunpoint in a robbery or participating in a crime
because our loved ones are held threatened with death is understandable and not
in itself morally bad: we plead duress and hope that we are not adjudged
morally responsible for our actions.
Behind the questions of authority and
obligation, and intertwined with the problem of ethical norms in a world devoid
of a natural order, is the question of the moral value of human life, the
importance or goodness of survival: when we are “forced” to do something bad,
we usually have a chance to resist, but perhaps at the cost of considerable
pain or even death. If the world holds no natural purpose or norms for us, is
it not good by default to do those things that preserve our life and avoid
those that threaten it? Or is the choice morally indifferent?
The physis-nomos or “nature-nurture” distinction is also closely
related to today’s “fact-value” distinction, the notion that all ethical norms
are purely conventional values or “value judgments” because their truth cannot
be discerned using our prized method of discovering the order of nature: the
scientific method. Though the fact-value distinction is historically a product
of the nineteenth century, its roots can be clearly seen in the philosophy of
Hobbes and Locke, and before them, Lucretius and the Epicureans.
Politics
Finally we
arrive at the subject matter of this course: politics. What are the questions
and issues peculiar to political inquiry or theory? Generally, we want to know
the source of political or governmental or legal authority and the proper functions of government.
It is useful again to begin by
referring to Aristotle’s view: politics is the study of the political or social
unit and of the order that is appropriate to it. The Greeks at the time of
Plato and Aristotle—that is, at the time political science originated—lived in
communities called poleis (singular, polis). Greek society in the sense of a nation or organized community of all
Greeks did not exist. Thus the polis was at once the “political” and the
“social” unit of order, as we would understand these terms today. Following Aristotle’s division, politics is
the study of what is right and wrong for the organized community, ethics
studies what is right and wrong for the individual. Politics necessarily
focuses on political and social order, on the relationships between the
individuals that make up the political and social unit. For Plato and
Aristotle, ethics also studied order—the right and wrong order of the various
parts of the individual’s soul. Modern political theorists often do not posit
an ordered soul, and some do not even posit the existence of a human soul, but
the general meaning of politics as the study of order continues to be quite
useful.
One’s view
of the order appropriate to the political unit is closely related to one’s view
of the purpose or proper function of the political unit. If we reject the notion
of a natural order and the idea that behavioral norms can and should be
grounded in either nature or God, then the purpose of political government is
pretty much up to us. It does appear, however, that some functions of
government are reasonably consistent with human nature and human capabilities.
It would be folly, perhaps, to give to government a function that is
objectively impossible to achieve, and since politics and government are
basically spheres of human action, it would be equally folly to attempt to
require or expect people to live a life or to have them order their actions in
a manner that is not consistent with their nature. If human beings are
basically self-interested, aggressively desirous animals, then any social goal
would probably require some order imposed on men from without: part, and
perhaps the main part, of government’s function would be to provide law and
order. If only a small minority of the population is so aggressively
self-interested, and most human beings are capable of spontaneously peaceful,
cooperative action, then perhaps government can aim at more ambitious ends: the
securing of a comfortable life, the development of human virtue, perhaps, or
even a religiously salvific life on earth.
If we accept
the ontological idea that an order of being or reality exists and that it
provides norms to men, who are part of that structure of reality, then the
proper purpose of government can perhaps be discerned by rational inquiry. If
man has a natural end or purpose, then politics may be part of the means to
achieve that purpose.
A related
question of particular importance to politics—and to law, the instrument of
government—is the question of authority: what is the source or basis of
political and legal authority? It is customary today to subject political and
legal norms to a moral standard. Thus, we condemn some policies and laws as
“immoral” and thus without obligatory force. But as we saw, classical
philosophers such as Aristotle made politics, not ethics, the master science or
ultimate standard. From this perspective, whether governmental policies and
laws are truly authoritative and creative of obligation and duty depends not on
their consistency with true ethical norms, but their consistency with true
political norms, a way of looking at the problem that is not common in today’s
world where “politics” more often than not is a dirty word, not a word standing
on truth and virtue.
Thus, our
inquiry into politics and government must be informed by our inquiries into the
other subjects: ontology and cosmology, epistemology, anthropology, and ethics.
It is the purpose of this course to help you find your way through these
subjects in order to arrive at some coherent, if only temporary, outlook
relating to politics. You will find, I believe, that once you begin to see the
connections between these subjects, you will not be content to look at
politics—domestic or international relations—in the same way again. As you
inquire into political philosophy, you will find, as Herakleitos said 2500
years ago, “I searched out myself.”
[1] “Phenomenon” is derived from phainomenon (φαίνομένων), which means “to appear.”
[2] "Philosophy" —from yet another Greek word: philosophia (φιλοσοφέω) which means "to love knowledge or wisdom, to pursue it."
[3] “What is Political Philosophy,” in Political Philosophy, ed. H. Gildin (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1975), 4.
[4] Ibid.
[5] On Duties, II.5. The connection between philosophy and the causes that underlie nature is still evident in the term “natural philosophy,” meaning generally natural science, that survives here and there on old buildings. The same meaning is carried in the old expression “natural history,” which recalls the original Greek meaning of the term “history” (Greek, ίστορέω; Latin, historia): to inquire into or about something. Discussion about the gods is literally “theology”: θεός λόγος.
[6] Republic, 578c. See similar statements at Republic 344e, 352d, 358d, and Gorgias, 458c, 500c.
[7] The term “philosophy” is also popularly used to mean “policy” or a characteristic approach or rationale for particular actions.
[8] In the “Seventh Letter,” which is generally acknowledged by scholars to be the work of Plato, Plato said that his philosophy “does not at all admit of verbal expression like other studies, but, as a result of continued application to the subject itself and communion therewith, it is brought to birth in the soul on a sudden, as light that is kindled by a leaping spark, and thereafter it nourishes itself.” 341c-d.
[9] Nicomachean Ethics, 1094a20-1094b4.
[10] New Science of Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952), 2.
[11] Political Philosophy, supra, 12, 4; see also Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 34 ("Originally, philosophy had been the humanizing quest for the eternal order, and hence it had been a pure source of humane inspiration and aspiration."). This conception of philosophy should be contrasted with the model put forward by John Locke and accepted by many today who see the philosopher’s proper vocation as “an under-labourer [employed] in clearing the ground a little, and removing some of the rubbish that lies in the way to knowledge.” “Epistle to the Reader,” in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding ( New York: Dover Publications, 1959), Volume I, p. 14.
[12] See, for example, Hitler and the Germans by Eric Voegelin or The Rebel by Albert Camus.
[13] The Sacred and the Profane, trans. Willard R. Trask (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1959), 10.
[14] Ibid., 20, 28.
[15] Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, chapter 5.
[16] Rousseau’s classic statement in Book One, chapter 3, of the Social Contract is worth reading.