A DISCOURSE
ON A SUBJECT PROPOSED BY THE ACADEMY OF
DIJON:
WHAT IS THE ORIGIN OF INEQUALITY AMONG
MEN,
AND IS IT AUTHORISED BY NATURAL LAW?
Jean Jacques Rousseau
1754
Translated by G. D. H. Cole, public
domain
[Excerpts on morality, identified by
the number of the part and paragraph of the discourse.]
Part
I. [34]It appears, at first
view, that men in a state of nature, having no moral relations or determinate
obligations one with another, could not be either good or bad, virtuous or
vicious; unless we take these terms in a physical sense, and call, in an
individual, those qualities vices which may be injurious to his preservation,
and those virtues which contribute to it; in which case, he would have to be
accounted most virtuous, who put least check on the pure impulses of nature.
But without deviating from the ordinary sense of the words, it will be proper
to suspend the judgment we might be led to form on such a state, and be on our
guard against our prejudices, till we have weighed the matter in the scales of
impartiality, and seen whether virtues or vices preponderate among civilised men; and whether their virtues do them more good
than their vices do harm; till we have discovered, whether the progress of the
sciences sufficiently indemnifies them for the mischiefs they do one another,
in proportion as they are better informed of the good they ought to do; or
whether they would not be, on the whole, in a much happier condition if they
had nothing to fear or to hope from any one, than as they are, subjected to
universal dependence, and obliged to take everything from those who engage to
give them nothing in return.
[35]Above all, let us not conclude,
with Hobbes, that because man has no idea of goodness, he must be naturally
wicked; that he is vicious because he does not know virtue; that he always
refuses to do his fellow-creatures services which he does not think they have a
right to demand; or that by virtue of the right he truly claims to everything
he needs, he foolishly imagines himself the sole proprietor of the whole
universe. Hobbes had seen clearly the defects of all the modern definitions of
natural right: but the consequences which he deduces from his own show that he
understands it in an equally false sense. In reasoning on the principles he
lays down, he ought to have said that the state of nature, being that in which the
care for our own preservation is the least prejudicial to that of others, was
consequently the best calculated to promote peace, and the most suitable for
mankind. He does say the exact opposite, in consequence of having improperly
admitted, as a part of savage man's care for self-preservation, the
gratification of a multitude of passions which are the work of society, and
have made laws necessary. A bad man, he says, is a robust child. But it remains
to be proved whether man in a state of nature is this robust child: and, should
we grant that he is, what would he infer? Why truly,
that if this man, when robust and strong, were dependent on others as he is
when feeble, there is no extravagance he would not be guilty of; that he would
beat his mother when she was too slow in giving him her breast; that he would
strangle one of his younger brothers, if he should be troublesome to him, or
bite the arm of another, if he put him to any inconvenience. But that man in
the state of nature is both strong and dependent involves two contrary
suppositions. Man is weak when he is dependent, and is his own master before he
comes to be strong. Hobbes did not reflect that the same cause, which prevents
a savage from making use of his reason, as our jurists hold, prevents him also
from abusing his faculties, as Hobbes himself allows: so that it may be justly
said that savages are not bad merely because they do not know what it is to be
good: for it is neither the development of the understanding nor the restraint
of law that hinders them from doing ill; but the peacefulness of their
passions, and their ignorance of vice: tanto plus in illis proficit vitiorum ignoratio, quam in his cognitio virtutis.2 There is another
principle which has escaped Hobbes; which, having been bestowed on mankind, to
moderate, on certain occasions, the impetuosity of egoism, or, before its
birth, the desire of self-preservation, tempers the ardour
with which he pursues his own welfare, by an innate repugnance at seeing a
fellow-creature suffer.3 I think I need not fear contradiction in holding man
to be possessed of the only natural virtue, which could not be denied him by
the most violent detractor of human virtue. I am speaking of compassion, which
is a disposition suitable to creatures so weak and subject to so many evils as
we certainly are: by so much the more universal and useful to mankind, as it
comes before any kind of reflection; and at the same time so natural, that the
very brutes themselves sometimes give evident proofs of it. Not to mention the
tenderness of mothers for their offspring and the perils they encounter to save
them from danger, it is well known that horses show a reluctance to trample on
living bodies. One animal never passes by the dead body of another of its
species: there are even some which give their fellows a sort of burial; while
the mournful lowings of the cattle when they enter
the slaughter-house show the impressions made on them by the horrible spectacle
which meets them. We find, with pleasure, the author of the Fable of the Bees
obliged to own that man is a compassionate and sensible being, and laying aside
his cold subtlety of style, in the example he gives, to present us with the
pathetic description of a man who, from a place of confinement, is compelled to
behold a wild beast tear a child from the arms of its mother, grinding its
tender limbs with its murderous teeth, and tearing its palpitating entrails
with its claws. What horrid agitation must not the eyewitness of such a scene
experience, although he would not be personally concerned! What anxiety would
he not suffer at not being able to give any assistance to the fainting mother
and the dying infant!
Part Two. [2]Man's first feeling was that of his own existence, and his first care that of self-preservation. The produce of the earth furnished him with all he needed, and instinct told him how to use it. Hunger and other appetites made him at various times experience various modes of existence; and among these was one which urged him to propagate his species — a blind propensity that, having nothing to do with the heart, produced a merely animal act. The want once gratified, the two sexes knew each other no more; and even the offspring was nothing to its mother, as soon as it could do without her.
[4]In proportion as the human race grew
more numerous, men's cares increased. The difference of soils, climates and
seasons, must have introduced some differences into their manner of living.
Barren years, long and sharp winters, scorching summers which parched the
fruits of the earth, must have demanded a new industry. On the seashore and the
banks of rivers, they invented the hook and line, and became fishermen and eaters
of fish. In the forests they made bows and arrows, and became huntsmen and
warriors. In cold countries they clothed themselves with the skins of the
beasts they had slain. The lightning, a volcano, or some lucky chance
acquainted them with fire, a new resource against the rigours
of winter: they next learned how to preserve this element, then how to
reproduce it, and finally how to prepare with it the flesh of animals which
before they had eaten raw.
[5]This repeated relevance of various beings to himself, and one to another, would naturally give rise in the human mind to the perceptions of certain relations between them. Thus the relations which we denote by the terms, great, small, strong, weak, swift, slow, fearful, bold, and the like, almost insensibly compared at need, must have at length produced in him a kind of reflection, or rather a mechanical prudence, which would indicate to him the precautions most necessary to his security.
[16]Everything now begins to change its aspect. Men, who have up to now been roving in the woods, by taking to a more settled manner of life, come gradually together, form separate bodies, and at length in every country arises a distinct nation, united in character and manners, not by regulations or laws, but by uniformity of life and food, and the common influence of climate. Permanent neighbourhood could not fail to produce, in time, some connection between different families. Among young people of opposite sexes, living in neighbouring huts, the transient commerce required by nature soon led, through mutual intercourse, to another kind not less agreeable, and more permanent. Men began now to take the difference between objects into account, and to make comparisons; they acquired imperceptibly the ideas of beauty and merit, which soon gave rise to feelings of preference. In consequence of seeing each other often, they could not do without seeing each other constantly. A tender and pleasant feeling insinuated itself into their souls, and the least opposition turned it into an impetuous fury: with love arose jealousy; discord triumphed, and human blood was sacrificed to the gentlest of all passions.
[17]As ideas and feelings succeeded one another, and heart and head
were brought into play, men continued to lay aside their original wildness;
their private connections became every day more intimate as their limits
extended. They accustomed themselves to assemble before their huts round a
large tree; singing and dancing, the true offspring of love and leisure, became
the amusement, or rather the occupation, of men and women thus assembled
together with nothing else to do. Each one began to consider the rest, and to wish to be considered
in turn; and thus a value came to be attached to public esteem. Whoever sang or
danced best, whoever was the handsomest, the strongest, the most dexterous, or
the most eloquent, came to be of most consideration; and this was the first
step towards inequality, and at the same time towards vice. From these first
distinctions arose on the one side vanity and contempt and on the other shame
and envy: and the fermentation caused by these new leavens ended by producing
combinations fatal to innocence and happiness.
[20]But it must be remarked that the
society thus formed, and the relations thus established among men, required of
them qualities different from those which they possessed from their primitive
constitution. Morality began to appear in human actions, and every one, before
the institution of law, was the only judge and avenger of the injuries done
him, so that the goodness which was suitable in the pure state of nature was no
longer proper in the new-born state of society. Punishments had to be made more
severe, as opportunities of offending became more frequent, and the dread of
vengeance had to take the place of the rigour of the
law. Thus, though men had become less patient, and their natural compassion had
already suffered some diminution, this period of expansion of the human
faculties, keeping a just mean between the indolence of the primitive state and
the petulant activity of our egoism, must have been the happiest and most
stable of epochs. The more we reflect on it, the more we shall find that this
state was the least subject to revolutions, and altogether the very best man
could experience; so that he can have departed from it only through some fatal
accident, which, for the public good, should never have happened. The example
of savages, most of whom have been found in this state, seems to prove that men
were meant to remain in it, that it is the real youth of the world, and that
all subsequent advances have been apparently so many steps towards the
perfection of the individual, but in reality towards the decrepitude of the
species.
[21]So long as men remained content
with their rustic huts, so long as they were satisfied with clothes made of the
skins of animals and sewn together with thorns and fish-bones, adorned
themselves only with feathers and shells, and continued to paint their bodies
different colours, to improve and beautify their bows
and arrows and to make with sharp-edged stones fishing boats or clumsy musical
instruments; in a word, so long as they undertook only what a single person
could accomplish, and confined themselves to such arts as did not require the
joint labour of several hands, they lived free,
healthy, honest and happy lives, so long as their nature allowed, and as they
continued to enjoy the pleasures of mutual and independent intercourse. But
from the moment one man began to stand in need of the help of another; from the
moment it appeared advantageous to any one man to have enough provisions for
two, equality disappeared, property was introduced, work became indispensable,
and vast forests became smiling fields, which man had to water with the sweat
of his brow, and where slavery and misery were soon seen to germinate and grow
up with the crops.